| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
6. It can be inferred from the passage as a whole that the author s purpose in the third paragraph is primarily to (A) cast doubt on the usefulness of Temperley s study of the London Pianoforte school (B) introduce a discussion of the coherency of the London Pianoforte school (C) summarize Ringer s argument about the London Pianoforte school (D) emphasize the complex nature of the musicological elements shared by members of the London Pianoforte school. (E) identify the unique contributions made to music by the London Pianoforte school 7. The author of the passage is primarily concerned with (A) explaining the influence of the development of the pianoforte on the music of Beethoven (B) describing Tempetley s view of the contrast between the development of piano music in England and the development of plano music elsewhere in Europe (C) presenting Temperley s evaluation1 of the impact of changes in piano construction on styles and forms of music composed in the era of the London Pianoforte school (D) considering an altermnative theory to that proposed by Ringer concerning the London Pianoforte school (E) discussing the contribution of Temperley s anthology to what is known of the history of the London Pianoforte school 8. It can be inferred that Temperley s anthology treats the London Pianoforte school as (A) a group of pianist-composers who shared certain stylistic principles and arustic creeds (B) a group of people who contributed to the development of piano music between 1766 and 1873 (C) a group of composers who influenced the music of Beethoven in the decades just before and just after 1800 (D) a series of compositions for the pianoforte published in the decades just before and just after 1800 (E) a series of compositions that had a significant influence on the music of the Continent in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries What is "law"? By what processes do judges arrive at opinions. those documents that justify2 their belief that the "law" dictates3 a conclusion one way or the other? These are among the oldest questions in (5) jurisprudence, debate about which has traditionally been dominated by representatives of two schools of thought: proponents4 of natural law, who see law as intertwined with a moral order independent of society s rules and mores5, and legal positivists, who see law (10) solely6 as embodying7 the commands of a society s ruling authority Since the early 1970s, these familiar questions have received some new and surprising answers in the legal academy. This novelty is in part a consequence of the (15) increasing influence there of academic disciplines and intellectual traditions previously8 unconnected with the study of law. Perhaps the most influential9 have been the answers given by the Law and Economics school. According to these legal economists10, law consists and (20) ought to consist of those rules that maximize a society s material wealth and that abet11 the efficient operation of markets designed to generate wealth. More controversial have been the various answers provided by members of the Critical Legal Studies movement (25) according to whom law is one among several cultural mechanisms12 by which holders13 of power seek to legitimate14 their domination. Drawing on related arguments developed in anthropology15, sociology, and history, the critical legal scholars contend that law is an (30) expression of power, but not, as held by the positivists, the power of the legitimate sovereign government. Rather, it is an expression of the power of elites16 who may have no legitimate authority, but who are intent on preserving the privileges of their race, class, or gender17. (35) In the mid-1970s, James Boyd White began to articulate yet another interdiseiplinary response to the traditional questions, and in so doing spawned18 what is now known as the Law and Literature movement White has insisted that law, particularly as it is (40) interpreted in judicial19 opinions, should be understood as an essentially20 literary activity. Judicial opinions should be read and evaluated not primarily as political acts or as atte mpts to maximize society s wealth through efficient rules, but rather as artistic (45) performances. And like all such performances, White argues, each judicial opinion attempts in its own way to promote a particular political or ethical21 value. In the recent Justice as Translation, White argues that opinion-writing should be regarded as an act of (50) "translation," and judges as "translators." As such, judges find themselves mediating22 between the authoritative23 legal text and the pressing legal problem that demands resolution. A judge must essentially "re-constitute" that text by fashioning a new one, which (55) is faithful to the old text but also responsive to and informed by the conditions, constraints, and aspirations of the world in which the new legal problem has arisen 点击收听单词发音
|
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
TAG标签:
- 发表评论
-
- 最新评论 进入详细评论页>>